Dictionary Definition
truth
Noun
1 a fact that has been verified; "at last he knew
the truth"; "the truth is the he didn't want to do it"
2 conformity to reality or actuality; "they
debated the truth of the proposition"; "the situation brought home
to us the blunt truth of the military threat"; "he was famous for
the truth of his portraits"; "he turned to religion in his search
for eternal verities" [syn: the true,
verity] [ant: falsity]
3 a true statement; "he told the truth"; "he
thought of answering with the truth but he knew they wouldn't
believe it" [syn: true
statement] [ant: falsehood]
4 the quality of nearness to the truth or the
true value; "he was beginning to doubt the accuracy of his
compass"; "the lawyer questioned the truth of my account" [syn:
accuracy] [ant:
inaccuracy]
5 United States abolitionist and feminist who was
freed from slavery and became a leading advocate of the abolition
of slavery and for the rights of women (1797-1883) [syn: Sojourner
Truth]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Pronunciation
- /tɹuːθ/, /tru:T/
- Rhymes: -uːθ
Noun
- The state or quality of being true to someone or something;
faithfulness,
fidelity.
- Truth to one's own feelings is all-important in life.
- A pledge of loyalty or faith.
- Conformity to fact or
reality; correctness, accuracy.
- There was some truth in his statement that he had no other choice.
- True facts, genuine depiction or statements of reality.
- The truth is that our leaders knew a lot more than they were letting on.
- That which is real, in
a deeper sense; spiritual or ‘genuine’ reality.
- "The truth is what is."
- Alcoholism and redemption led me finally to truth.
- 1820: Beauty is truth, truth beauty, - that is all / Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know. — John Keats, ‘Ode on a Grecian Urn’
- "The truth is what is."
- Something acknowledged to be true; a true statement or axiom.
- Hunger and jealousy are just eternal truths of human existence.
- 1813: It is a truth universally acknowledged, that a single man in possession of a good fortune, must be in want of a wife. — Jane Austen, Pride and Prejudice
Antonyms
Related terms
Translations
the state or quality of being true to someone or
something
- German: Wahrheit
- Irish: fírinne
- Russian: верность
a pledge of loyalty or faith
conformity to fact or reality
- Finnish: totuus
- German: Wahrheit
- Irish: fírinne
- Russian: правда, истина
true facts
- Finnish: totuus
- German: Wahrheit
- Irish: fírinne
- Russian: правда, истина
that which is real
- German: Wahrheit
- Irish: fírinne
something acknowledged to be true
- Finnish: totuus
- German: Wahrheit
- Irish: fírinne
- Russian: истина
- ttbc Arabic:
- ttbc Aramaic:
- ttbc Breton: gwirionez
- ttbc Bulgarian: истина (ístina)
- ttbc Cebuano: kamatuoran
- ttbc Chinese: 事實, 事实 (shìshí)
- ttbc Croatian: istina
- ttbc Czech: pravda
- ttbc Danish: sandhed
- ttbc Dutch: waarheid
- ttbc Esperanto: vero
- ttbc Estonian: tõde
- ttbc Ewe: nyateƒe
- ttbc French: vérité
- ttbc Greek: αλήθεια
- ttbc Hebrew: אמת (emet)
- ttbc Hungarian: igazság
- ttbc Icelandic: sannleikur
- ttbc Ido: vera
- ttbc Indonesian: kebenaran
- ttbc Italian: verità
- ttbc Japanese: 真実 (しんじつ, shinjitsu), 本当 (ほんとう, hontō), 心理 (しんり, shinri)
- ttbc Kannada: ನನ್ನಿ
- ttbc Korean: 진실 (jinsil), 진리 (jilli), 참됨 (chamdoem)
- ttbc Kurdish:
- ttbc Latin: veritas
- ttbc Macedonian: вистина (vistina)
- ttbc Malayalam: സത്യം (sathyam), നേര് (neru)
- ttbc Northern Sami: duohtavuohta
- ttbc Norwegian: sannhet
- ttbc Occitan: vertat
- ttbc Persian: (dorosti)
- ttbc Polish: prawda
- ttbc Portuguese: verdade
- ttbc Romanian: adevăr
- ttbc Serbian: istina
- ttbc Slovak: pravda
- ttbc Slovene: resnica
- ttbc Spanish: verdad
- ttbc Swahili: kweli (class 9/10)
- ttbc Welsh: gwir
Extensive Definition
The meaning of
the word truth extends from honesty, good faith,
and sincerity in
general, to agreement with fact or reality in particular. The term
has no single definition about which the
majority of professional philosophers and scholars agree. Various
theories of truth
continue to be debated. There are differing claims on such
questions as what constitutes truth; how to define and identify
truth; the roles that revealed and acquired knowledge play; and
whether truth is subjective,
relative,
objective,
or absolute.
This article introduces the various perspectives and claims,
both today and throughout history.
The major theories of truth
The proper basis for deciding how words, symbols,
ideas and beliefs may properly be considered true, whether by a
single person or an entire society, is a principal focus of the
five substantive theories introduced below. These theories each
present perspectives that are widely shared by published scholars.
There also have more recently arisen "deflationary"
or "minimalist" theories of truth based on the idea that the
application of a term like true to a statement does not assert
anything significant about it, for instance, anything about its
nature, but that the label truth is a tool of discourse used to
express agreement, to emphasize claims, or to form certain types of
generalizations. Some post-modern
thinkers assert that what passes for truth is in fact, merely, the
mass consensus of the public. This would entail that no effort, or
application of theory or experiment, is required to arrive at
truth, which is in effect only a by-product of social change.
Substantive theories
Correspondence theory
Correspondence theories state that true beliefs
and true statements correspond to the actual state of affairs. This
type of theory attempts to posit a relationship between thoughts or
statements on the one hand, and things or objects on the other. It
is a traditional model which goes back at least to some of the
classical Greek philosophers such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. This
class of theories holds that the truth or the falsity of a
representation is determined in principle solely by how it relates
to objective
reality, by whether it accurately describes that reality. For
example, there is a true
distance to the moon when we humans attempt to go there, and this
true distance is necessary to know so that the journey can be
successfully made.
Correspondence theory states that truth is a
matter of accurately copying "objective reality" and then
representing it in thoughts, words and other symbols. A major
proponent of this theory is the Christian
philosopher Thomas
Aquinas, who said that "Truth is the conformity of the
intellect with things." He said that real things participate in the
act of being of the Creator God who is Subsistent
Being, Intelligence, and Truth. Thus, these beings possess the
light of intelligibility and are knowable. These things (beings;
reality) are the
foundation of the truth that is found in the human mind, when it
acquires knowledge of things, first through the senses, then through the understanding and the
judgement done by
reason. For Aquinas,
human intelligence
("intus", within and "legere", to read) has the capability to reach
the essence and existence of things because it
is an immaterial, spiritual power.
Coherence theory
More modern theorists have stated that the idea
behind correspondence theory cannot be achieved independently of
some analysis of additional factors. Proponents of several of these
other theories have gone farther to assert that there are yet other
issues necessary to the analysis, such as language and its
translation to other languages, interpersonal power struggles,
community interactions, personal biases and other factors involved
in deciding what is seen as truth.
For coherence theories in general, truth requires
a proper fit of elements within a whole system. Very often, though,
coherence is taken to imply something more than simple logical
consistency; often there is a demand that the propositions in a
coherent system lend mutual inferential support to each other. So,
for example, the completeness and comprehensiveness of the
underlying set of concepts is a critical factor in judging the
validity and usefulness of a coherent system. A pervasive tenet of
coherence theories is the idea that truth is primarily a property
of whole systems of propositions, and can be ascribed to individual
propositions only according to their coherence with the whole.
Among the assortment of perspectives commonly regarded as coherence
theory, theorists differ on the question of whether coherence
entails many possible true systems of thought or only a single
absolute system.
Some variants of coherence theory are claimed to
characterize the essential and intrinsic properties of formal
systems in logic and mathematics. However, formal reasoners are
content to contemplate
axiomatically independent and sometimes mutually contradictory
systems side by side, for example, the various alternative
geometries. On the whole, coherence theories have been
criticized as lacking justification in their application to other
areas of truth, especially with respect to assertions about the
natural
world, empirical
data in general, assertions about practical matters of psychology
and society, especially when used without support from the other
major theories of truth.
Coherence theories distinguish the thought of
rationalist
philosophers, particularly of Spinoza, Leibniz, and
G.W.F.
Hegel, along with the British philosopher F.H.
Bradley. They have found a resurgence also among several
proponents of logical
positivism, notably Otto Neurath
and Carl
Hempel.
Constructivist theory
Social
constructivism holds that truth is constructed by social
processes, is historically and culturally specific, and that it is
in part shaped through the power struggles within a community.
Constructivism views all of our knowledge as "constructed," because
it does not reflect any external "transcendent" realities (as a
pure correspondence theory might hold). Rather, perceptions of
truth are viewed as contingent on convention, human perception, and
social experience. It is believed by constructivists that
representations of physical and biological reality, including
race, sexuality,
and gender are socially
constructed. Giambattista
Vico was among the first to claim that history and culture were
man-made. Vico's epistemological orientation
gathers the most diverse rays and unfolds in one axiom--verum ipsum
factum--"truth itself is constructed." Hegel, Garns, and
Marx were
among the other early proponents of the premise that truth is
socially constructed.
Consensus theory
Consensus theory holds that truth is whatever is agreed upon,
or in some versions, might come to be agreed upon, by some
specified group. Such a group might include all human beings, or a
subset thereof consisting
of more than one person.
Among the current advocates of consensus theory
as a useful accounting of the concept of "truth" is the philosopher
Jürgen
Habermas. Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed
upon in an ideal speech situation. Among the current strong critics
of consensus theory is the philosopher Nicholas
Rescher.
Pragmatic theory
The three most influential forms of the pragmatic
theory of truth were introduced around the turn of the 20th century
by Charles S.
Peirce, William
James, and John Dewey.
Although there are wide differences in viewpoint among these and
other proponents of pragmatic theory, they hold in common that
truth is verified and confirmed by the results of putting one's
concepts into practice.
Peirce
defines truth as follows: "Truth is that concordance of an abstract
statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation
would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance the
abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its
inaccuracy and one-sidedness, and this confession is an essential
ingredient of truth." This statement emphasizes Peirce's view that
ideas of approximation, incompleteness, and partiality, what he
describes elsewhere as fallibilism and "reference
to the future", are essential to a proper conception of truth.
Although Peirce uses words like concordance and correspondence to
describe one aspect of the pragmatic sign
relation, he is also quite explicit in saying that definitions
of truth based on mere correspondence are no more than nominal
definitions, which he accords a lower status than real
definitions.
William
James's version of pragmatic theory, while complex, is often
summarized by his statement that "the 'true' is only the expedient
in our way of thinking, just as the 'right' is only the expedient
in our way of behaving." By this, James meant that truth is a
quality the value of which is confirmed by its effectiveness when
applying concepts to actual practice (thus, "pragmatic").
John Dewey,
less broadly than James but more broadly than Peirce, held that
inquiry, whether scientific, technical, sociological, philosophical
or cultural, is self-corrective over time if openly submitted for
testing by a community of inquirers in order to clarify, justify,
refine and/or refute proposed truths.
Minimalist (deflationary) theories
A number of philosophers reject the thesis that
the concept or term truth refers to a real property of sentences or
propositions. These philosophers are responding, in part, to the
common use of truth predicates (e.g., that some particular thing
"...is true") which was particularly prevalent in philosophical
discourse on truth in the first half of the 20th century. From this
point of view, to assert the proposition “'2 + 2 = 4' is true” is
logically equivalent to asserting the proposition “2 + 2 = 4”, and
the phrase “is true” is completely dispensable in this and every
other context. These positions are broadly described
- as deflationary theories of truth, since they attempt to deflate the presumed importance of the words "true" or truth,
- as disquotational theories, to draw attention to the disappearance of the quotation marks in cases like the above example, or
- as minimalist theories of truth.
Whichever term is used, deflationary theories can
be said to hold in common that "[t]he predicate 'true' is an
expressive convenience, not the name of a property requiring deep
analysis."
Performative theory of truth
Attributed to P. F.
Strawson is the performative theory of truth which holds that
to say "'Snow is white' is true" is to perform the speech act of
signaling one's agreement with the claim that snow is white (much
like nodding one's head in agreement). The idea that some
statements are more actions than communicative statements is not as
odd as it may seem. Consider, for example, that when the bride says
"I do" at the appropriate time in a wedding, she is performing the
act of taking this man to be her lawful wedded husband. She is not
describing herself as taking this man. In a similar way, Strawson
holds: "To say a statement is true is not to make a statement about
a statement, but rather to perform the act of agreeing with,
accepting, or endorsing a statement. When one says 'It's true that
it's raining,' one asserts no more than 'It's raining.' The
function of [the statement] 'It's true that...' is to agree with,
accept, or endorse the statement that 'it's raining.'"
Redundancy and related theories
According to the
redundancy theory of truth, asserting that a statement is true
is completely equivalent to asserting the statement itself. For
example, making the assertion that " 'Snow is white' is
true" is equivalent to asserting "Snow is white". Redundancy
theorists infer from this premise that truth is a redundant
concept; that is, it is merely a word that is traditionally used in
conversation or writing, generally for emphasis, but not a word
that actually equates to anything in reality. This theory is
commonly attributed to Frank P.
Ramsey, who held that the use of words like fact and truth was
nothing but a roundabout way of asserting
a proposition, and that treating these words as separate problems
in isolation from judgment was merely a "linguistic muddle".
A variant of redundancy theory is the
disquotational theory which uses a modified form of Tarski's
schema: To say that '"P" is true' is to say that P. Yet another
version of deflationism is the
prosentential theory of truth, first developed by Dorothy
Grover, Joseph Camp, and Nuel Belnap
as an elaboration of Ramsey's claims. They argue that sentences
like "That's true", when said in response to "It's raining", are
prosentences,
expressions that merely repeat the content of other expressions. In
the same way that it means the same as my dog in the sentence My
dog was hungry, so I fed it, That's true is supposed to mean the
same as It's raining — if you say the latter and I then
say the former. These variations do not necessarily follow Ramsey
in asserting that truth is not a property, but rather can be
understood to say that, for instance, the assertion "P" may well
involve a substantial truth, and the theorists in this case are
minimalizing only the redundancy or prosentence involved in the
statement such as "that's true." or under all possible interpretations, as
contrasted to a synthetic claim (or fact) which is only true in this
world as it has historically unfolded. Logical truths are
necessarily true. A proposition such as “If p
and q, then p.” and the proposition “All husbands are married.” are
considered to be logical truths because they are true because of
their meanings and not
because of any facts of the world. They are such that they could
not be untrue.
Logic is concerned
with the patterns in reason that can help tell us if a
proposition is true
or not. However, logic does not deal with truth in the absolute
sense, as for instance a metaphysician does.
Logicians use formal
languages to express the truths which they are concerned with,
and as such there is only truth under some interpretation or truth
within some logical
system.
Truth in mathematics
There are two main approaches to truth in mathematics. They are the model theory of truth and the proof theory of truth.Historically, with the nineteenth century
development of Boolean
algebra mathematical models of logic began to treat "truth",
also represented as "T" or "1", as an arbitrary constant. "Falsity"
is also an arbitrary constant, which can be represented as "F" or
"0". In propositional
logic, these symbols can be manipulated according to a set of
axioms and rules of
inference, often given in the form of truth
tables.
In addition, from at least the time of Hilbert's
program at the turn of the twentieth century to the proof of
Gödel's
theorem and the development of the Church-Turing
thesis in the early part of that century, true statements in
mathematics were generally assumed to be those statements which are
provable in a formal axiomatic system.
The works of Kurt
Gödel, Alan Turing,
and others shook this assumption, with the development of
statements that are true but cannot be proven within the system.
Two examples of the latter can be found in Hilbert's
problems. Work on Hilbert's
10th problem led in the late twentieth century to the
construction of specific Diophantine
equations for which it is undecidable whether they have a
solution, or even if they do, whether they have a finite or
infinite number of solutions. More fundamentally, Hilbert's
first problem was on the continuum
hypothesis. Gödel and Paul
Cohen showed that this hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved
using the standard axioms
of set
theory and a finite number of proof steps. In the view of some,
then, it is equally reasonable to take either the continuum
hypothesis or its negation as a new axiom.
Semantic theory of truth
The semantic
theory of truth has as its general case for a given language:
- 'P' is true if and only if P
Logician and philosopher Alfred
Tarski developed the theory for formal languages (such as
formal
logic). Here he restricted it in this way: no language could
contain its own truth predicate, that is, the expression is true
could only apply to sentences in some other language. The latter he
called an object language, the language being talked about. (It
may, in turn, have a truth predicate that can be applied to
sentences in still another language.) The reason for his
restriction was that languages that contain their own truth
predicate will contain paradoxical sentences like the Liar: This
sentence is not true. See The Liar
paradox. As a result Tarski held that the semantic theory could
not be applied to any natural language, such as English, because
they contain their own truth predicates.
Donald Davidson used it as the foundation of his truth-conditional
semantics and linked it to radical
interpretation in a form of coherentism.
Bertrand
Russell is credited with noticing the existence of such
paradoxes even in the best symbolic formalizations of mathematics
in his day, in particular the paradox that came to be named after
him, Russell's
paradox. Russell and Whitehead
attempted to solve these problems in Principia
Mathematica by putting statements into a hierarchy of types,
wherein a statement cannot refer to itself, but only to statements
lower in the hierarchy. This in turn led to new orders of
difficulty regarding the precise natures of types and the
structures of conceptually possible type systems
that have yet to be resolved to this day.
Kripke's theory of truth
Saul Kripke contends that a natural language can in fact contain its own truth predicate without giving rise to contradiction. He showed how to construct one as follows:- Begin with a subset of sentences of a natural language that contains no occurrences of the expression "is true" (or "is false"). So The barn is big is included in the subset, but not " The barn is big is true", nor problematic sentences such as "This sentence is false".
- Define truth just for the sentences in that subset.
- Then extend the definition of truth to include sentences that predicate truth or falsity of one of the original subset of sentences. So "The barn is big is true" is now included, but not either "This sentence is false" nor "The barn is big is true' is true".
- Next, define truth for all sentences that predicate truth or falsity of a member of the second set. Imagine this process repeated infinitely, so that truth is defined for The barn is big; then for "The barn is big is true"; then for "The barn is big is true' is true", and so on.
Notice that truth never gets defined for
sentences like This sentence is false, since it was not in the
original subset and does not predicate truth of any sentence in the
original or any subsequent set. In Kripke's terms, these are
"ungrounded." Since these sentences are never assigned either truth
or falsehood even if the process is carried out infinitely,
Kripke's theory implies that some sentences are neither true nor
false. This contradicts the Principle
of bivalence: every sentence must be either true or false.
Since this principle is a key premise in deriving the Liar paradox,
the paradox is dissolved.
Notable philosophers' views
Ancient philosophers
The ancient Greek
origins of the words "true" and "truth" have some consistent
definitions throughout great spans of history that were often
associated with topics of logic, geometry, mathematics, deduction, induction, and natural
philosophy.
Socrates',
Plato's and
Aristotle's ideas
about truth are commonly seen as consistent with correspondence
theory. In his Metaphysics,
Aristotle stated: “To say of what is that it is not, or of what is
not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and
of what is not that it is not, is true”. The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy proceeds to say of
Aristotle:
Aristotle sounds much more like a genuine
correspondence theorist in the Categories (12b11, 14b14), where he
talks of “underlying things” that make statements true and implies
that these “things” (pragmata) are logically structured situations
or facts (viz., his sitting, his not sitting). Most influential is
his claim in De Interpretatione (16a3) that thoughts are
“likenessess” (homoiosis) of things. Although he nowhere defines
truth in terms of a thought's likeness to a thing or fact, it is
clear that such a definition would fit well into his overall
philosophy of mind.
In the Upanishads of
ancient
India, truth is Sat
(pronounced Sah't), the one reality and existence, which is
directly experienced by the Rishi or sage (see
also Gandhi
section below). The Rishi discovers that which exists, Sat, as the
truth of one's own being, the Atma
or self, and as the truth of the being of God, Ishvara.
Medieval philosophers
In early
Islamic philosophy, Avicenna (Ibn
Sina) defined truth as:
What corresponds in the mind
to what is outside it.
Avicenna elaborated on his definition of truth in
his Metaphysics:
The truth of a thing is the
property of the being of each thing which has been established in
it.
Following Avicenna, and also Augustine and
Aristotle, Thomas
Aquinas stated in his Disputed Questions on Truth:
A natural thing, being placed
between two intellects, is called true insofar as it conforms to
either. It is said to to be true with respect to its conformity
with the divine intellect insofar as it fulfills the end to which
it was ordained by the divine intellect... With respect to its
conformity with a human intellect, a thing is said to be true
insofar as it is such as to cause a true estimate about
itself.
Thus, for Thomas, the truth of the human
intellect (logical truth) is based on the truth in things
(ontological truth). Following this, he wrote an elegant
re-statement of Aristotle's view in his Summa I.16.1:
Veritas est adæquatio
intellectus et rei. (Truth is the conformity of the intellect to
the things.)
Modern philosophers
Kant
Immanuel
Kant discussed the correspondence theory of truth According to
Kant, the definition of truth as correspondence is a "mere verbal
definition", here making use of Aristotle's distinction between a
nominal definition, a definition in name only, and a real
definition, a definition
that shows the true cause or essence of the thing whose term is
being defined. From Kant's account of the history, the
definition of truth as correspondence was already in dispute from
classical times, the "skeptics" criticizing the "logicians" for a
form of circular reasoning, though the extent to which the
"logicians" actually held such a theory is not evaluated.
While objective truths are final and static,
subjective truths are continuing and dynamic. The truth of one's
existence is a living, inward, and subjective experience that is
always in the process of becoming. The values, morals, and
spiritual approaches a person adopts, while not denying the
existence of objective truths of those beliefs, can only become
truly known when they have been inwardly appropriated through
subjective experience. Thus, Kierkegaard criticizes all systematic
philosophies which attempt to know life or the truth of existence
via theories and objective knowledge about reality. As Kierkegaard
claims, human truth is something that is continually occurring, and
a human being cannot find truth separate from the subjective
experience of one's own existing, defined by the values and
fundamental essence that consist of one's way of life.
Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche believed the search for truth or 'the will to truth' was a consequence of the will to power of philosophers. He thought that truth should be used as long as it promoted life and the will to power, and he thought untruth was better than truth if it had this life enhancement as a consequence. As he wrote in Beyond Good and Evil, "The falseness of a judgment is to us not necessarily an objection to a judgment... The question is to what extent it is life-advancing, life-preserving, species-preserving, perhaps even species-breeding..." (aphorism 4). He proposed the will to power as a truth only because according to him it was the most life affirming and sincere perspective one could have.Robert Wicks discusses Nietzsche's basic view of
truth as follows: Some scholars regard Nietzsche's 1873 unpublished
essay, "On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense" ("Über Wahrheit und
Lüge im außermoralischen Sinn") as a keystone in his thought. In
this essay, Nietzsche rejects the idea of universal constants, and
claims that what we call "truth" is only "a mobile army of
metaphors, metonyms, and anthropomorphisms." His view at this time
is that arbitrariness completely prevails within human experience:
concepts originate via the very artistic transference of nerve
stimuli into images; "truth" is nothing more than the invention of
fixed conventions for merely practical purposes, especially those
of repose, security and consistence.
Heidegger
Gandhi
Mohandas "Mahatma" Gandhi dedicated his life to the wider purpose of discovering truth, or Satya. He tried to achieve this by learning from his own mistakes and conducting experiments on himself. He called his autobiography The Story of My Experiments with Truth. Gandhi stated that the most important battle to fight was overcoming his own demons, fears, and insecurities. Gandhi summarized his beliefs first when he said "God is Truth". He would later change this statement to "Truth is God".Whitehead
Alfred North Whitehead a British mathematician who became an American philosopher, said: "There are no whole truths; all truths are half-truths. It is trying to treat them as whole truths that play the devil".The logical progression or connection of this
line of thought is to conclude that truth can lie, since half-truths are
deceptive and may lead to a false conclusion.
Nishida
According to Kitaro Nishida, "knowledge of things in the world begins with the differentiation of unitary consciousness into knower and known and ends with self and things becoming one again. Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing (of truth) that directs knowing, the willing that directs action, and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing."Fromm
Erich Fromm finds that trying to discuss truth as "absolute truth" is sterile and that emphasis ought to be placed on "optimal truth". He considers truth as stemming from the survival imperative of grasping one's environment physically and intellectually, whereby young children instinctively seek truth so as to orient themselves in "a strange and powerful world". The accuracy of their perceived approximation of the truth will therefore have direct consequences on their ability to deal with their environment. Fromm can be understood to define truth as a functional approximation of reality. His vision of optimal truth is described partly in "Man from Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics" (1947), from which excerpts are included below.- the dichotomy between 'absolute = perfect' and 'relative = imperfect' has been superseded in all fields of scientific thought, where "it is generally recognized that there is no absolute truth but nevertheless that there are objectively valid laws and principles".
- In that respect, "a scientifically or rationally valid statement means that the power of reason is applied to all the available data of observation without any of them being suppressed or falsified for the sake of a desired result". The history of science is "a history of inadequate and incomplete statements, and every new insight makes possible the recognition of the inadequacies of previous propositions and offers a springboard for creating a more adequate formulation."
- As a result "the history of thought is the history of an ever-increasing approximation to the truth. Scientific knowledge is not absolute but optimal; it contains the optimum of truth attainable in a given historical period." Fromm furthermore notes that "different cultures have emphasized various aspects of the truth" and that increasing interaction between cultures allows for these aspects to reconcile and integrate, increasing further the approximation to the truth.
Foucault
Truth, for Michel Foucault, is problematic when any attempt is made to see truth as an "objective" quality. He prefers not to use the term truth itself but "Regimes of Truth". In his historical investigations he found truth to be something that was itself a part of, or embedded within, a given power structure. Thus Foucault's view shares much in common with the concepts of Nietzsche. Truth for Foucault is also something that shifts through various episteme throughout history.Baudrillard
Jean Baudrillard considered truth to be largely simulated, that is pretending to have something, as opposed to dissimulation, pretending to not have something. He took his cue from iconoclasts who he claims knew that images of God demonstrated the fact that God did not exist. Baudrillard wrote in "Precession of the Simulacra":-
- The simulacrum is
never that which conceals the truth—it is the truth which conceals
that there is none. The simulacrum is true.
- —Ecclesiastes
- The simulacrum is
never that which conceals the truth—it is the truth which conceals
that there is none. The simulacrum is true.
Some example simulacra that Baudrillard cited
were: that prisons simulate the "truth" that society is free;
scandals (eg, Watergate)
simulate that corruption is corrected; Disney simulates that the
U.S. itself is an adult place. One must remember that though such
examples seem extreme, such extremity is an important part of
Baudrillard's philosophy. For a less extreme example consider how
movies, almost without exception, end with the bad guy being
punished, thus drilling into the viewers that successful
businessmen and politicians are good or, if not, will be caught.
conscience, freedom, and religion. He thinks that this
self-limitation, which "amputates" the mind's capacity to answer
fundamental questions such as man's origin and purpose, dishonors
reason and is contradictory to the modern acclamation of science,
whose basis is the power of reason.
For Ratzinger, truth and love are identical. And if well
understood, according to him, this is "the surest guarantee of
tolerance." Similarly, d'Holbach,
in System of
Nature, contrasts Mythology as an attempt to convey truth with
theology as an attempt
to obfuscate it.
Religious truth
Most religious traditions have a body of doctrine
that adherents of that religion view as truth. This may take the
form of a creed or catechism, it may refer to a book such as the
Bible or the
Koran, or it
may be an unwritten code shared by believers. Unlike scientific
truth or observed truth, religious truth often makes the claim of
being either revealed or inspired by God.
When there is a clash between religious truth and
scientific truth, various methods have been used to reconcile the
two. During the Middle Ages,
for example, there was conflict between Roman
Catholic dogma on the one hand and an emerging body of scientific knowledge on the
other. Sometimes the established church sought to suppress
scientific truth, as in the case of Galileo, but
sometimes the two truths were allowed to coexist, which led to the
doctrine of the two truths. According to this compromise, there is
a lesser truth, scientific truth, which holds that the earth orbits
the sun, and a greater truth, religious truth, that holds that the
earth is the fixed center of the universe. According to the
doctrine of the two truths, these two truths were both true in
their own sphere.
The modern Roman Catholic church has rejected the
doctrine of two truths, and accepts as true all scientific truth.
However, Christian Fundamentalism
claims that religious truth should be accepted by scientists, and
that if science were not corrupt it would recognize, for example,
the occurrence of a universal flood. Thus the conflict between
religious truth and scientific truth continues.
Scientific truth
See also Empirical truth.Science seeks to approach truth through the
scientific
method. Strictly speaking, the scientific method never "proves"
a theory or shows that it is definitely true. Except when it comes
to directly observable facts, the scientific method never claims to
reveal "the truth"; rather, it attempts to approach the truth by
continuously refining theories so that they better approximate the
truth.
Someone following the scientific method begins by
collecting facts. Scientifically speaking, a fact is a directly
observable, reproducible truth. A
purported truth doesn't qualify as a fact if it's based on the
observation of a single person. To qualify as a scientific fact, it
must be based on repeated observations by many different
scientists. For example, "When on Earth a rock is picked up from
the ground and then released, it falls." qualifies as a scientific
fact: it's directly observable and it's reproducible, because
anyone can test it by picking up a rock and then letting go.
After collecting facts, a scientist formulates a
hypothesis, a
possible explanation for the facts. A hypothesis makes a suggestion
as to what mechanism or relationship lies behind the observed
facts. This relationship itself doesn't need to be directly
observable. To qualify as scientific, a hypothesis must be falsifiable: that is, one
must be able to imagine an experiment which, if carried out, could
disprove the hypothesis.
The scientist then tests the hypothesis by making
further observations (sometimes in a highly controlled environment
such as a laboratory). Roughly speaking, if repeated observations
support a hypothesis, then it qualifies as a theory.
The above is a very simplified account of the
scientific method. In actual practice, most scientists begin their
investigations by collecting more than raw facts. For example, many
scientific hypothesis take an already-accepted scientific theory as
one of the "facts" that support it or that it seeks to explain. For
example, many theories in modern biology take the theory
of evolution as part of their supporting evidence.
Examples of scientific theories which are
accepted by almost all professional scientists include the germ
theory of disease, Einstein's theory
of relativity, and the theory of evolution. A scientific theory
is often mathematical in
nature.
“Nothing is too wonderful to be true, if it be
consistent with the laws of nature, and in such things as these,
experiment is the best test of such consistency.”, Schwinger
1969 quoting from M.
Faraday.
Nomenclature and etymology
English truth is from Old English tríewþ, tréowþ, trýwþ, Middle English trewþe, cognate to Old High German triuwida, Old Norse tryggð. Like troth, it is a -th nominalisation of the adjective true (Old English tréowe).English true is from Old
English (West Saxon)
(ge)tríewe, tréowe,
cognate to Old Saxon
(gi)trûui, Old High
German (ga)triuwu (Modern
German treu "faithful"), Old Norse
tryggr, Gothic
triggws, all from a Proto-Germanic
*trewwj- "having good faith".
Old Norse , holds the semantic
field "faith, word of honour; religious faith, belief" (archaic
English troth "loyalty,
honesty, good faith", compare ).
Thus, 'truth' involves both the quality of
"faithfulness, fidelity, loyalty, sincerity, veracity", and that of
"agreement with fact or
reality", in Anglo-Saxon
expressed by sōþ.
All Germanic languages besides English have
introduced a terminological distinction between truth "fidelity"
and truth "factuality". To express "factuality", North
Germanic opted for nouns derived from sanna "to assert,
affirm", while continental West
Germanic (German and Dutch) opted for continuations of wâra
"faith, trust, pact" (cognate to Slavic věra "(religious) faith",
but influenced by Latin verus). Romance
languages use terms continuing Latin veritas, while Greek with
aletheia and Slavic
with pravda have
unrelated terms.
Notes
References
- Aristotle, "The Categories", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 1–109 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
- Aristotle, "On Interpretation", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 111–179 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
- Aristotle, "Prior Analytics", Hugh Tredennick (trans.), pp. 181–531 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1938.
- Aristotle, "On the Soul" (De Anima), W. S. Hett (trans.), pp. 1–203 in Aristotle, Volume 8, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, UK, 1936.
- Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
- Baldwin, James Mark (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York, NY.
- Baylis, Charles A. (1962), "Truth", pp. 321–322 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Benjamin, A. Cornelius (1962), "Coherence Theory of Truth", p. 58 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK. Includes papers by James, Ramsey, Russell, Tarski, and more recent work.
- Chandrasekhar, Subrahmanyan (1987), Truth and Beauty. Aesthetics and Motivations in Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
- Chang, C.C., and Keisler, H.J., Model Theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, Netherlands, 1973.
- Chomsky, Noam (1995), The Minimalist Program, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Church, Alonzo (1962a), "Name Relation, or Meaning Relation", p. 204 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Church, Alonzo (1962b), "Truth, Semantical", p. 322 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Clifford, W.K. (1877), "The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays". (Prometheus Books, 1999) http://www.infidels.org/library/historical/w_k_clifford/ethics_of_belief.html
- Dewey, John (1900–1901), Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901, Donald F. Koch (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL.
- Dewey, John (1932), Theory of the Moral Life, Part 2 of John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY, 1908. 2nd edition, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1932. Reprinted, Arnold Isenberg (ed.), Victor Kestenbaum (pref.), Irvingtion Publishers, New York, NY, 1980.
- Dewey, John (1938), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938),Holt and Company, New York, NY. Reprinted, John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 12: 1938, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1986.
- Field, Hartry (2001), Truth and the Absence of Fact, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
- Foucault, Michel (1997), Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Volume 1, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, Paul Rabinow (ed.), Robert Hurley et al. (trans.), The New Press, New York, NY.
- Garfield, Jay L., and Kiteley, Murray (1991), Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, Paragon House, New York, NY.
- Gupta, Anil (2001), "Truth", in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, UK.
- Haack, Susan (1993), Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, UK.
- Habermas, Jürgen (1976), "What Is Universal Pragmatics?", 1st published, "Was heißt Universalpragmatik?", Sprachpragmatik und Philosophie, Karl-Otto Apel (ed.), Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Reprinted, pp. 1–68 in Jürgen Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, Thomas McCarthy (trans.), Beacon Press, Boston, MA, 1979.
- Habermas, Jürgen (1990), Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (trans.), Thomas McCarthy (intro.), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Habermas, Jürgen (2003), Truth and Justification, Barbara Fultner (trans.), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Horwich, Paul, (1988), Truth, 2nd edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
- James, William (1904), A World of Pure Experience.
- James, William (1907), Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures on Philosophy, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
- James, William (1909), The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
- James, William (1912), Essays in Radical Empiricism. Cf. Chapt. 3, "The Thing and its Relations", pp. 92–122.
- Kant, Immanuel (1800), Introduction to Logic. Reprinted, Thomas Kingsmill Abbott (trans.), Dennis Sweet (intro.), Barnes and Noble, New York, NY, 2005.
- Kirkham, Richard L. (1992), Theories of Truth, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Kneale, W., and Kneale, M. (1962), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press, London, UK, 1962. Reprinted with corrections, 1975.
- Kreitler, Hans, and Kreitler, Shulamith (1972), Psychology of the Arts, Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2004), "Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey", British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12 (4) 2004, 705–718, PDF.
- Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP vol.para.
- Peirce, C.S. (1877), "The Fixation of Belief", Popular Science Monthly 12 (1877), 1–15. Reprinted (CP 5.358–387), (CE 3, 242–257), (EP 1, 109–123). Eprint.
- Peirce, C.S. (1901), "Truth and Falsity and Error" (in part), pp. 718–720 in J.M. Baldwin (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, vol. 2. Reprinted, CP 5.565–573.
- Polanyi, Michael (1966), The Tacit Dimension, Doubleday and Company, Garden City, NY.
- Quine, W.V. (1956), "Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes", Journal of Philosophy 53 (1956). Reprinted, pp. 185–196 in Quine (1976), Ways of Paradox.
- Quine, W.V. (1976), The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays, 1st edition, 1966. Revised and enlarged edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1976.
- Quine, W.V. (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View, Logico-Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Quine, W.V. (1980 b), "Reference and Modality", pp. 139–159 in Quine (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View.
- Rajchman, John, and West, Cornel (ed., 1985), Post-Analytic Philosophy, Columbia University Press, New York, NY.
- Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–170. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1990.
- Ramsey, F.P. (1990), Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
- Rawls, John (2000), Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, Barbara Herman (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
- Russell, Bertrand (1912), The Problems of Philosophy, 1st published 1912. Reprinted, Galaxy Book, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 1959. Reprinted, Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY, 1988.
- Russell, Bertrand (1918), "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism", The Monist, 1918. Reprinted, pp. 177–281 in Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, UK, 1956. Reprinted, pp. 35–155 in The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL, 1985.
- Russell, Bertrand (1956), Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, UK, 1956. Reprinted, Routledge, London, UK, 1992.
- Russell, Bertrand (1985), The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL.
- Smart, Ninian (1969), The Religious Experience of Mankind, Charles Scribner's Sons, New York, NY.
- Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J.H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1956. 2nd edition, John Corcoran (ed.), Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN, 1983.
- Wallace, Anthony F.C. (1966), Religion: An Anthropological View, Random House, New York, NY.
Reference works
- Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
- Blackburn, Simon (1996), The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1994. Paperback edition with new Chronology, 1996. Cited as ODP.
- Runes, Dagobert D. (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ, 1962.
- Webster's New International Dictionary of the English Language, Second Edition, Unabridged (1950), W.A. Neilson, T.A. Knott, P.W. Carhart (eds.), G. & C. Merriam Company, Springfield, MA. Cited as MWU.
- Webster's Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary (1983), Frederick C. Mish (ed.), Merriam–Webster Inc., Springfield, MA. Cited as MWC.
See also
- Aletheia
- Asha
- Belief
- Confirmation holism
- contextualism
- Degrees of truth
- Disposition
- Eclecticism
- Half-truth
- Honesty
- Imagination
- Independence
- Inquiry
- Interpretation
- Invariance
- Knowledge
- Liar paradox
- Lie
- Lie-to-children
- Normative science
- Objectivity
- Paradox
- Perspectivism
- Philalethia
- Physical symbol system
- Reality
- Relativism
- Religion
- Slingshot argument
- Statistical independence
- Tautology (logic)
- Tautology (rhetoric)
- Truthiness
- Unity of the proposition
- Veritas
Truth in logic
- Fuzzy logic
- Logic
- Logical value
- Modal logic
- Multi-valued logic
- Principle of bivalence
- Truth conditions
- Truth function
- Truth table
- Criteria of truth
Theories of truth
- Coherentism
- Coherence theory of truth
- Consensus theory of truth
- Correspondence theory of truth
- Deflationary theory of truth
- Epistemic theories of truth
- Indefinability theory of truth
- Pragmatic theory of truth
- Redundancy theory of truth
- Semantic theory of truth
Major theorists
- Aristotle
- Thomas Aquinas
- Augustine of Hippo
- J.L. Austin
- Brand Blanshard
- John Dewey
- Hartry Field
- Gottlob Frege
- Jürgen Habermas
- Martin Heidegger
- Paul Horwich
- William James
- Harold Joachim
- Saul Kripke
- Friedrich Nietzsche
- Charles Sanders Peirce
- Plato
- Karl Popper
- W.V. Quine
- Frank P. Ramsey
- Bertrand Russell
- Socrates
- P.F. Strawson
- Alfred Tarski
- Ludwig Wittgenstein
External links
truth in Arabic: حقيقة
truth in Guarani: Mañei
truth in Min Nan: Chin-lí
truth in Belarusian (Tarashkevitsa):
Ісціна
truth in Catalan: Veritat
truth in Czech: Pravda
truth in Danish: Sandhed
truth in German: Wahrheit
truth in Estonian: Tõde
truth in Spanish: Verdad
truth in Esperanto: Vero
truth in French: Vérité
truth in Irish: Fírinne
truth in Korean: 진리
truth in Croatian: Istina
truth in Indonesian: Kebenaran
truth in Icelandic: Sannleikur
truth in Italian: Verità
truth in Hebrew: אמת ושקר (פילוסופיה)
truth in Kurdish: Rastî
truth in Latin: Veritas
truth in Lithuanian: Tiesa
truth in Hungarian: Igazság
truth in Macedonian: Вистина
truth in Malay (macrolanguage): Kebenaran
truth in Dutch: Waarheid
truth in Japanese: 真理
truth in Norwegian: Sannhet
truth in Occitan (post 1500): Vertat
truth in Polish: Prawda
truth in Portuguese: Verdade
truth in Romanian: Adevăr
truth in Quechua: Chiqap
truth in Russian: Истина
truth in Albanian: E vërteta
truth in Simple English: True
truth in Slovenian: Resnica
truth in Serbian: Истина
truth in Serbo-Croatian: Istina
truth in Finnish: Totuus
truth in Swedish: Sanning
truth in Thai: ความจริง
truth in Turkish: Gerçek
truth in Ukrainian: Істина
truth in Walloon: Vraiye
truth in Yiddish: אמת
truth in Chinese: 真理
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
a priori truth, absolute certainty, absolute
credibility, absoluteness, accomplished
fact, accuracy,
actuality, actually, assurance, assuredness, authenticity, axiom, brocard, candor, certain knowledge,
certainness,
certainty, certitude, correctness, credibility, dead certainty,
definiteness,
determinacy,
determinateness,
dictate, dictum, fact, facts, factuality, fait accompli,
formula, genuineness, golden rule,
gospel, grim reality,
historicity, in
fact, in truth, ineluctability, inerrability, inerrancy, inevitability, infallibilism, infallibility, law, necessity, nonambiguity, noncontingency, not a
dream, objective existence, positiveness, postulate, precision, predestination, predetermination,
principium, principle, probatum, proposition, proved fact,
reality, really, rightness, rule, self-evident truth, settled
principle, sureness,
surety, theorem, trueness, truism, truly, truth-loving,
truth-speaking, truth-telling, truthfulness, unambiguity, unequivocalness,
universal truth, univocity, unmistakableness,
veraciousness,
veracity, veridicality, verity